29. After the discussion of the nature of moral
virtues in general, Aristotle sets out to discuss the specific characteristics
of single moral virtues in particular. To organize the
material, it is useful to consider Aristotle’s discussion as following a
certain system of classification of these virtues.
30. As we have seen above, Aristotle first
distinguishes excellence in all sorts of operation from excellence in the
rational operations, that is, irrational and rational virtues, and then within
the sphere of rational virtues, intellectual from moral virtues.
31. The specific moral virtues discussed by
Aristotle then can be subdivided into personal, as opposed to social virtues,
the first dealing with right choices concerning personal conduct whether in a
social context or not, while the latter concerning behavior in some specific
social context.
32. The former group comprises courage and
temperance, the virtue concerning the ability to properly handle fear, the
latter concerning the ability to properly handle pleasure. The latter group
comprises virtues concerned with money (liberality and magnificence), those
concerned with honor (pride, healthy ambition), those with anger (good temper,
indignation), with social intercourse (friendliness, truthfulness, ready wit),
and the quasi-virtue of the feeling of shame.
33. The following table summarizes Aristotle’s
classification of moral virtues. (Note that the terminology provided here comes
from another translation; the point is that you recognize the corresponding
discussion in your translation.)
Type |
Concerning |
Vice of Deficiency |
Virtuous Mean |
Vice of Excess |
Personal
virtues |
Fear |
Cowardice |
Courage |
Rashness |
Pleasure |
Insensibility |
Temperance |
Self-indulgence |
|
Social
virtues |
Money |
Stinginess |
Liberality |
Prodigality |
Pettiness |
Magnificence |
Vulgarity |
||
Honor |
Lack of Ambition |
Healthy Ambition |
Over-ambition |
|
Humbleness |
Pride |
Vainglory |
||
Anger |
Lack of Spirit |
Good Temper |
Irascibility |
|
Callousness |
Indignation |
Spitefulness |
||
Social
intercourse |
Surliness |
Friendliness |
Obsequiousness |
|
Self-Deprecation |
Sincerity |
Boastfulness |
||
Boorishness |
Wittiness |
Buffoonery |
||
Shamelessness |
Modesty |
Bashfulness |
34. In addition to these, Aristotle deals in more
detail with justice, which has a special status, since the notion of justice in
one way is much broader then that of a specific moral
virtue, indeed, in this broad sense it coincides with the notion of moral
virtue in general, with the connotation of the exercise of all moral virtues
towards one’s neighbor (i.e., one’s fellow humans).
35. So Aristotle in the first place distinguishes
universal justice from particular justice. The former
is nothing but virtue in general in its exercise toward one’s neighbor
[1130a6], while the latter is a particular kind of
moral virtue, concerning hitting the mean in terms of the equality of certain
quantities, as opposed to their inequality in either way.
36. The specific forms of justice are determined
by the kind of equality to be aimed at by the corresponding just act.
37. In the case of distributive justice the
equality in question is the equality of the proportions between the amounts of
goods distributed (g1:g2) and
the greatness of the merits of the recipients (m1:m2),
that is to say, a just distribution in this sense is one that observes the
proportionality: g1:g2=m1:m2. For example, this sort of justice is at work when shareholders receive
their dividends in proportion to their quantifiable “merits”, namely, their
investments.
38. In the case of commutative justice the
equality to be observed is the equality of the amounts exchanged. This is the
kind of justice to be observed in commerce, where a fair deal is one in which
goods of equal value are exchanged.
39. In the case of rectificatory justice
the equality to be observed is the equality of the results, when the just
action is one that corrects some unjust inequality. This type of justice is to
be exercised most commonly in lawsuits, where the unjust inequality is caused
by the damage inflicted by one person on another, and the legal system is
supposed to rectify the situation by compensating the plaintiff at the expense
of the culprit.
40. However, since all these forms of justice are
to be realized in a working society in some form of political and legal system,
these specific kinds of justice are the manifestations of overall political
and legal justice, or the lack thereof, in a given
society.
41. Political and legal justice manifest
themselves in the justice of the laws and their execution in
a given society, insofar as it is the laws of that society which will
provide the standard by which all particular actions will be evaluated as
legally just or unjust. But then, if the laws themselves are definitive of
justice in a given society, and we know that different
societies in different regions and different historical periods have widely
different legal systems, will this render justice relative to time and place?
Would not this reasoning have the consequence that justice is a matter of
convention depending on the geographically and historically contingent
legislation of a given society? Could there be, then, any justification for
international law other than the military and/or economic power of powerful
nations? Would not this justify the cynical claim ‘might makes right’?
42. To all these questions Aristotle’s answer
would be a definitive ‘No’. In his view, we need to distinguish further between
the historically and geographically relative positive law of several
nations in several historical periods, and the universal natural law of
all human societies. In view of this distinction, even though the variable laws
of positive legal systems are definitive of positive legal justice in a given society in a given historical period, they
themselves are to be judged for their justice in terms of the precepts of
natural law: any positive law is just and is thus justifiable only to the
extent it is a particular realization of the precepts of natural law.
43. But then, who is to say what those precepts
of natural law are, and whether some positive legislation is in fact a particular realization of those precepts or rather goes
against them? Who is to judge the natural justice or injustice of positive
legislation? What can possibly be the standard for this judgment?
44. In fact, this question is still not the most
universal question that one can raise concerning the objectivity of value
judgments. After all, as we have seen, justice, despite its comprehensiveness,
is just one among a number of moral virtues, all
specifying right and wrong with respect to their corresponding actions.
45. We have also seen that the important common
element in Aristotle’s discussion of moral virtues in general is that they are
all presented as enabling us to choose the mean between two bad extremes,
excess and defect, with regard to handling things to
be desired or to be avoided. Avoidance of things to be desired is just as bad
as desire of things to be avoided, and so the extremes in either direction are
naturally and intrinsically bad.
46. So with respect to all human actions in
general, the question of the objectivity of value-judgments is this: is there
an objective standard by which we can tell right from wrong, virtuous from
non-virtuous, intrinsically good from intrinsically bad?
47. As a matter of fact, we get a hint of
Aristotle’s answer to this question early on, in his fully articulated
definition of moral virtue: “Virtue, then, is a state of character concerned
with choice, lying in a mean, i.e., the mean relative to us, this being
determined by a rational principle by which the man of practical wisdom would
determine it”. [1006b36]
48. It is “the man of practical wisdom” who is
going to be able to set the standards we are looking for.
49. The rationale for this answer is given by
Aristotle’s discussion of intellectual virtues and their relationships to moral
virtues.
50. In general, as we have said, intellectual
virtues, as opposed to moral virtues, are concerned not with doing things, but
with knowing things. But knowledge itself has several kinds, some more
theoretical and more universal, being the perfection of what Aristotle calls
the scientific part of the soul, some more practical and more
particular, being the perfection of what Aristotle calls the calculative part
of the soul.
51. Accordingly, intellectual virtues are
distinguished with respect to their characteristic objects. The purely theoretical intellectual virtues are: (1) scientific
knowledge, (2) intuitive reason, and (3) philosophic wisdom. (1) Scientific
knowledge for Aristotle is the knowledge of necessary and universal aspects of
things, based on strict deductions. (2) Intuitive reason is the understanding
of the first principles of demonstration from which scientific knowledge is
deduced. (3) Philosophic wisdom is the combination of the two with respect to
knowledge of the highest things and most universal first principles.
52. The practically oriented intellectual virtues
are (4) art and (5) prudence or practical wisdom. (4) Art in Aristotle’s
interpretation is the craft of the craftsman that enables him to produce
something. (5) Prudence, however, is the more general intellectual ability to
secure some human good, by applying some universal knowledge to some particular situation, offering the alternatives for
deliberation before the will would chose to carry out some particular course of
action.
53. Prudence, therefore, is the mediating virtue
between the purely theoretical virtues and the moral virtues. Philosophical
wisdom, combining intuitive reason and scientific knowledge establishes the
general philosophical understanding of the nature of being and goodness in
general, and man’s good in this hierarchical order of being in
particular, specifying what is the characteristic perfection of human
nature in the nature of things. Given this philosophical, theoretical
understanding of what is the good for man in general, prudence will have to evaluate any concrete situation, and determine
the best means for achieving some particular end as eventually leading to this
overarching end. (Note that this may also require skill in some art. Indeed,
one may also want to consider equity in this context, as being the specific
kind of prudence of the judge who knows how to serve the spirit of the law in a
particular situation, occasionally even against its
dead letter).
54. Thus, in any actual situation of choice, the
virtues are supposed to work in concert, in a certain hierarchical order,
providing the integrity of character determining the choice: presented by
prudence with a number of alternatives for achieving a
certain end, the will, predisposed by the moral virtues to aim at the mean
between bad extremes, after some deliberation makes the particular choice that
initiates the action. But the deliberation is always guided by prudence, which
evaluates the possible alternatives with the end in view.
55. In this scheme, therefore, prudence is acting
like the conductor of an orchestra, organizing the activity of the musicians
for the sake of achieving harmony; the virtues act like the score prescribing
the best individual sounds to be aimed at by the musicians, who are like the
specific skills materializing some particular action.
The decision of a musician to sound his instrument is like the act of will
making a particular choice, in which, however, he has
to heed the conductor (prudence), who knows when and how it is the best for
this particular act to take place. But the conductor is still not the one who
wrote the score, his activities are still subordinate to the score of the
composer, who discovered the best harmony to be achieved by contemplating the
nature of harmony itself, just like philosophical wisdom discovers what is the
best for man, by considering the harmony of all things in general.