Augustine Summary
- Since St. Augustine’s mature philosophical ideas are primarily
stemming from the Neo-Platonic tradition, we began our considerations with
a brief survey of Platonism.
- Plato’s central tenet is his theory of Forms. Although the
primary motivation for this theory can be derived from the epistemological
need to account for the possibility of a priori knowledge (i.e.,
necessary, universal knowledge that can be gained on the basis of
understanding and reasoning alone, such as mathematical knowledge, as
opposed to a posteriori, contingent, empirical, factual knowledge),
the theory plays a central role in all philosophical disciplines
(metaphysics-physics – being, logic-epistemology – truth, and ethics – goodness).
Cf. BK, pp. 114-133, esp. 117-124; City of God, VIII, 1-12.
- However, Plato’s original theory is demonstrably inconsistent,
as Plato himself realized in his Parmenides. (See the reconstructed
arguments online, in the class folder. Make sure you understand them all,
and that you are able to reproduce them, if needed.)
- As a result, in the Neo-Platonic tradition, Plato’s universal
exemplars for each distinct perfection became “concentrated” in the
absolutely simple perfection of the One, whose perfection unfolds in a
hierarchy of emanations of ever decreasing perfection, through the World
Soul, to human souls, and to the forms of material beings imposing some
partial order on chaotic formless matter. It is this idea of an
ontological hierarchy that is the most appealing to Augustine’s Christian
thought, identifying Plotinus’ One with the Supreme Being and Goodness,
the Christian God, whose eternal ideas will take on the function of
Plato’s Forms, as the universal archetypes of God’s creation. (See the section
on Divine Ideas in my article on “The Medieval
Problem of Universals” URL: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/universals-medieval/.)
- But besides finding this “natural match” between Platonic
metaphysics and the Christian idea of God’s relation to His creation (to
be sure, despite substantial disagreements on important details, see cf.
Spade, Survey,
pp. 40-50.), Augustine was very strongly influenced by Platonic
epistemological and ethical ideas as well.
- We first focused on one particular epistemological argument, in
the context of a larger moral-theological argument, in Augustine’s “On the
Free Choice of the Will”. Here I provide the outline of the larger
argument; you have the details of the epistemological argument in my
article on universals.
- In the first book of “On the Free Choice of the Will”,
Augustine and his interlocutor, Evodius, delved into the problem of the
origin of evil in the world. This clearly is a serious
problem for a Christian, who can see the obvious conflict in the
conception of a world manifestly containing horrendous evils, despite its
being the creation of an omnipotent, omniscient, and absolutely benevolent
God. According to the conclusion of the first book, it is certainly not
God who is to blame for the presence of evil, but rather man, who abuses
his God-given free will to do wrong.
- But then the question naturally arises: if God gave free will,
and he could foresee that man would abuse it, why didn’t He prevent evil
from arising by simply not giving free will to man in the first place?
(For the Augustinian answer check The
Origin of Moral Evil.)
- Addressing the further problems stemming from this consideration
is the main topic of the second book. In order to solve the inconsistency
between free will’s being the source of evil and its being God’s gift, the
interlocutors have to go back to check their original assumptions, namely,
whether free will is really God’s gift, indeed, whether there is a God in
the first place, to give such a (dubious) gift.
- The starting point of the argument in c. 3 is the absolute
certainty of one’s own existence. (Augustine’s favorite kind of certainty,
exploited time and again in his writings from the youthful “Against the
Academicians”, written specifically against the skepticism of the New
Academy, to the late “The City of God”. The idea is to have a great career
in modern philosophy after Descartes’ famous cogito ergo sum.)
- The subsequent considerations in cc. 3-6 are designed to
establish (a) that there is a an objective hierarchical arrangement of
things in nature (an issue we shall deal with in greater detail); (b) that
reason is on the top of this hierarchy, and (c) that if there is something
superior to reason, then it is either God, or something to which God is
superior; whence, either way, if something is superior to reason, then God
exists.
- Chapters 7-14 are designed to prove that there is something
superior to reason, namely, the eternal truths of number (c. 8) and of
wisdom (cc. 9-14). It is in this context that we find Augustine’s
“embedded” epistemological argument mentioned in 6 above. The important
point of the argument (reconstructed here: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/universals-medieval/#5.2)
is that our knowledge of mathematical truths is not derivable from
experience, whence we must have received it from a supernatural source. This
is the characteristic Augustinian theory of illumination, which will have
a long and bright career in the Middle Ages and in early modern
rationalism.
- Chapters 9-14 are analogous considerations concerning other a
priori truths, the “rules of wisdom”, which Augustine shows to be
superior to reason, insofar as reason cannot judge them whether they ought
to be the way they are (they simply have to be the way they
are, and reason can just enjoy if it manages to discover them
-- cf. BK, pp. 89-90 and http://www.fordham.edu/gsas/phil/klima/phil180/PlatoinMath.html);
reason rather judges other things, inferior and/or equal to itself, in
accordance with these rules, namely, whether these things are the way
they ought to be – this is again the Platonic use of Forms and the
eternal truths they validate as norms or standards by which we judge
things whether they live up to them. (We’ll discuss the issue of the
relationship between Forms or Divine Ideas and eternal truths and Truth
Itself in more detail later.)
- Chapter 15 finally draws the conclusion that God exists. Note
Evodius’ reaction: “my inner voice shouts” – this is the ecstatic Platonic
moment of the sudden flash of understanding, mentioned in the (perhaps
spurious, but doctrinally quite authentic) 7th letter of Plato.
- This conclusion allows the interlocutors to return to the
ethical considerations that prompted this “excursion”. Chapters 16-17
establish that all being, and hence, all order and perfection derives from
God. Note the analogy of the craftsman who follows the (mathematical!)
rules of his art, to God the Creator (cf. the picture on p. 105 of BK.).
This is again an issue we’ll spend some time on. For now, to see the significance
of the issue, check out (yes, again!) Spade’s Survey, c. 4,
especially pp. 45-47.
- Finally, the closing chapters of our selection deal with the
issue that since moral evil is the lack of the proper direction of the
will, and a lack, a defect, a deformity cannot come from the giver of
perfection and form, evil cannot come from God. Evil is rather just the
deformity and defectiveness of a God-given good thing, the free will of a
rational creature. This is another definitive Platonic-Augustinian theme:
evil is just the absence/deprivation of the good (malum est privatio
boni ) – and so this is another issue that we shall dwell on for some
time. (For later developments of the idea see (yes, again) my lecture note
on Boethius : http://www.fordham.edu/gsas/phil/klima/lectures.htm#Boethius;
we shall have to revisit this issue several times, in several contexts, so
it is not a waste of your time if you ponder it time and again.)
- Given the ontological hierarchy that provides the frame of
reference for the proper direction of the will, and the realization that
this proper direction is “upwards”, one task naturally emerging for a
human being in this life is obvious: the task is to find out exactly what
realizes in this life the “uplifting” of the soul, its approximation of
divine perfection to the extent that this is possible at all within the
confines of our finite nature. This is what Augustine attempts to
characterize through the analysis of the journey of one particular soul in
this life, the soul he knows best, his own. At the end of the analysis of
this soul’s travel through time, when it has finally reached its reachable
destination here, namely, peace in God, Augustine is in a position to look
back on his entire life from an entirely new vantage point, mimicking the
vantage point of God over His creation. This is what provides Augustine
with an opportunity of a profound reflection on the difference between
temporal being, the natural mode of existence of everything in physical
reality, and eternity, the mode of existence of God. (For further details
see Time
and Eternity in Augustine, and BK. 99-113.